사용자:이원룡/번역실/승인투표

위키백과, 우리 모두의 백과사전.
On an approval ballot, the voter can vote for any number of candidates.

Approval voting is a single-winner voting system| used for elections. Each voter may vote for (approve of) as many of the candidates as they wish. The winner is the candidate receiving the most votes. Each voter may vote for any combination of candidates and may give each candidate at most one vote.[1]

승인투표는 선거를 위해 사용되는 1인 승자 투표 시스템이다. 각각의 투표자는 원하는 후보에 복수로 투표할 수 있다. 가장 많은 표를 얻은 자가 당선자가 된다.

Approval voting is a form of range voting with the range restricted to two values, 0 and 1. Approval voting can be compared to plurality voting| without the rule that discards ballots which vote for more than one candidate.

The system was described in 1976 by Guy Ottewell and also by Robert J. Weber, who coined the term "approval voting." It was more fully published in 1978 by political scientist Steven Brams and mathematician Peter Fishburn.[2] Approval voting is used by some professional societies. Voting systems which incorporated aspects of approval voting have been used historically.

사용 Uses[편집]

승인투표 방식은 Mathematical Association of America (1986)[3], The Institute of Management Sciences (1987),[4] American Statistical Association (1987)[5], Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (1987)에서 사용하였다.

According to Steven J. Brams and Peter C. Fishburn, only the IEEE has rescinded the decision.

Steven J. Brams와 Peter C. Fishburn에 따르면, 오직 IEEE만 이 방식을 폐지했다.

They report the IEEE Executive Director, Daniel J. Senese, as stating that approval voting was abandoned in 2002 because "few of our members were using it and it was felt that it was no longer needed."

IEEE의 Executive Director인 Daniel J. Senese에 따르면, 그들은 2002년에 승인투표제를 폐지했다. 그 이유는 "회원들이 거의 사용하지 않으며, 더이상 그 방식이 필요하지 않아서"라고 한다.

Unlike the situation with MAA and ASA, Approval Voting was implemented by the IEEE board and rescinded by the board.[6]

Historically, several voting methods which incorporate aspects of approval voting have been used:

  • In the 13th through 18th centuries, the Republic of Venice elected the Doge of Venice using a multi-stage process that featured random selection and voting which allowed approval of multiple candidates and required a supermajority[7][8].
  • According to Steven J. Brams, approval voting was used in 19th century England.[9]
  • The selection of the Secretary-General| of the United Nations has involved rounds of approval polling to help discover and build a consensus before a formal vote is held in the Security Council.[10]
  • Bucklin Voting was used in the United States for some years. Bucklin is a ranked method, but if the first rank, which allowed only one vote, fails to find a majority winner, votes from the next rank are added in, so the election becomes more like an election with approval voting.

예제 Example[편집]

틀:Tenn voting example

테네시에는 100명의 주민이 살고 있고, 네 후보중 2명의 선호하는 후보에 투표하였다고 가정하면, 다음의 결과가 나올 수 있다 (더 복잡한 경우는 아래에 기술함):

  • Memphis: 42
  • Nashville: 68 당선됨
  • Chattanooga: 58
  • Knoxville: 32

Effect on elections[편집]

The effect of this system as an electoral reform measure is not without critics. Instant-runoff voting advocates like the Center for Voting and Democracy argue that approval voting would lead to the election of "lowest common denominator" candidates disliked by few, and liked by few,[출처 필요] but this could also be seen as an inherent strength against demagoguery in favor of a discreet popularity.[출처 필요] In an editorial, approval voting advocates Steven Brams and Dudley R. Herschbach predict that approval voting should increase voter participation, prevent minor-party candidates from being spoilers, and reduce negative campaigning. [11]

One study [12] showed that approval voting would not have chosen the same two winners as plurality voting (Chirac and Le Pen) in France's presidential election of 2002| (first round) - it instead would have chosen Chirac and Jospin. This seems a more reasonable result[출처 필요] since Le Pen was a radical who lost to Chirac by an enormous margin in the second round.

A generalized version of the Burr dilemma applies to approval voting when two candidates are appealing to the same subset of voters. Although approval voting differs from the voting system used in the Burr dilemma, approval voting can still leave candidates and voters with the generalized dilemma of whether to compete or cooperate.[13][14]

Approval voting usually elects Condorcet winners in practice.[15]

Strategic voting[편집]

Sincere voting[편집]

Approval voting experts describe sincere votes as those "... that directly reflect the true preferences of a voter, i.e. , that do not report preferences 'falsely.' " [16] They also give a specific definition of a sincere approval vote in terms of the voter's ordinal preferences| as being any vote that, if it votes for one candidate, it also votes for any more preferred candidate. This definition allows a sincere vote to treat strictly preferred candidates the same, ensuring that every voter has at least one sincere vote. The definition also allows a sincere vote to treat equally preferred candidates differently. When there are two or more candidates, every voter has at least three sincere approval votes to choose from. Two of those sincere approval votes do not distinguish between any of the candidates: vote for none of the candidates and vote for all of the candidates. When there are three or more candidates, every voter has more than one sincere approval vote that distinguishes between the candidates.

예제 Examples[편집]

위에서 기술한 정의를 바탕으로, 예를들어 갑을병정 네 후보가 있다면, 투표자는 다음과 같이 투표할 수 있다:

  • 갑을병정 모두에 투표
  • 갑을병에만 투표
  • 갑을에만 투표
  • 갑에만 투표
  • 아무에도 투표하지 않음

If the voter instead equally prefers B and C, while A is still the most preferred candidate and D is the least preferred candidate, then all of the above votes are sincere and the following combination is also a sincere vote:

  • vote for A and C

Strategy with ordinal preferences[편집]

A sincere voter with multiple options for voting sincerely still has to choose which sincere vote to use. Voting strategy is a way to make that choice, in which case strategic approval voting includes sincere voting, rather than being an alternative to it.[17] This differs from other voting systems that typically have a unique sincere vote for a voter.

When there are three or more candidates, the winner of an approval voting election can change, depending on which sincere votes are used. In some cases, approval voting can sincerely elect any one of the candidates, including a Condorcet winner and a Condorcet loser, without the voter preferences changing. To the extent that electing a Condorcet winner and not electing a Condorcet loser is considered desirable outcomes for a voting system, approval voting can be considered vulnerable to sincere, strategic voting.[18] In one sense, conditions where this can happen are robust and are not isolated cases.[19] On the other hand, the variety of possible outcomes has also been portrayed as a virtue of approval voting, representing the flexibility and responsiveness of approval voting, not just to voter ordinal preferences, but cardinal utilities as well.[20]

Dichotomous preferences[편집]

Approval voting avoids the issue of multiple sincere votes in special cases when voters have dichotomous preferences. For a voter with dichotomous preferences, approval voting is strategy-proof (also known as strategy-free).[21] When all voters have dichotomous preferences and vote the sincere, strategy-proof vote, approval voting is guaranteed to elect the Condorcet winner, if one exists.[22] However, having dichotomous preferences when there are three or more candidates would not be typical. It would be an unlikely situation for all voters to have dichotomous preferences when there are more than a few voters.[17]

Having dichotomous preferences means that a voter has bi-level preferences for the candidates. All of the candidates are divided into two groups such that the voter is indifferent between any two candidates in the same group and any candidate in the top-level group is preferred to any candidate in the bottom-level group.[23] A voter that has strict preferences between three candidates -- prefers A to B and B to C -- does not have dichotomous preferences.

Being strategy-proof for a voter means that there is a unique way for the voter to vote that is a strategically best way to vote, regardless of how others vote. In approval voting, the strategy-proof vote, if it exists, is a sincere vote.[16]

Approval threshold[편집]

Another way to deal with multiple sincere votes is to augment the ordinal preference model with an approval or acceptance threshold. An approval threshold divides all of the candidates into two sets, those the voter approves of and those the voter does not approve of. A voter can approve of more than one candidate and still prefer one approved candidate to another approved candidate. Acceptance thresholds are similar. With such a threshold, a voter simply votes for every candidate that meets or exceeds the threshold.[17]

With threshold voting, it is still possible to not elect the Condorcet winner and instead elect the Condorcet loser when they both exist. However, according to Steven Brams, this represents a strength rather than a weakness of approval voting. Without providing specifics, he advocates that the pragmatic judgements of voters about which candidates are acceptable should take precedence over the Condorcet criterion and other social choice criteria.[24]

Strategy with cardinal utilities[편집]

Voting strategy under approval is guided by two competing features of approval voting. On the one hand, approval voting fails the later-no-harm criterion, so voting for a candidate can cause that candidate to win instead of a more preferred candidate. On the other hand, approval voting satisfies the monotonicity criterion, so not voting for a candidate can never help that candidate win, but can cause that candidate to lose to a less preferred candidate. Either way, the voter can risk getting a less preferred election winner. A voter can balance the risk-benefit trade-offs by considering the voter's cardinal utilities, particularly von Nuemann-Morgenstern utilities, and the probabilities of how others will vote.

A rational voter model| described by Myerson| and Weber specifies an approval voting strategy that votes for those candidates that have a positive prospective rating.[25] This strategy is optimal in the sense that it maximizes the voter's expected utility|, subject to the constraints of the model and provided the number of other voters is sufficiently large.

An optimal approval vote will always vote for the most preferred candidate and not vote for the least preferred candidate. However, an optimal vote can require voting for a candidate and not voting for a more preferred candidate.

Other strategies are also available and will coincide with the optimal strategy in special situations. For example:

  • Vote for the candidates that have above average utility. This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy if the voter has no knowledge of how other voters will vote.[26]
  • Vote for any candidate that is more preferred than the expected winner and also vote for the expected winner if the expected winner is more preferred than the expected runner-up. This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy if there are three or fewer candidates of if the pivot probability for a tie between the expected winner and expected runner-up is sufficiently large compared to the other pivot probabilities.
  • Vote for the most preferred of the two leading candidates. This strategy coincides with the optimum strategy if the pivot probabilities for any other candidate being in a leading tie are sufficiently small and if the voter's most preferred candidate is one of the two leading candidates.
  • Vote for the most preferred candidate. This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy when there is only one candidate with a positive prospective rating.

Another strategy is to vote for the top half of the candidates, the candidates that have an above-median utility. When the voter has no knowledge of how other voters will vote, the strategy will maximize the voter's power or efficacy, meaning that it will maximize the probability that the voter will make a difference in deciding which candidate wins.[27]

Optimal strategic approval voting fails to satisfy the Condorcet criterion and can elect a Condorcet loser|. Strategic approval voting can guarantee electing the Condorcet winner| in some special circumstances. For example, if all voters are rational and cast a strategically optimal vote based on a common knowledge of how all the other voters vote except for small-probability, statistically independent errors in recording the votes, then the winner will be the Condorcet winner, if one exists.[28]

Strategy examples[편집]

In the example| election described earlier, assume that the voters in each faction share the following von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities, fitted to the interval between 0 and 100. The utilities are consistent with the rankings given earlier and reflect a strong preference each faction has for choosing its city, compared to weaker preferences for other factors such as the distance to the other cities.

Voter utilities for each candidate city
  Candidates  
Faction of Voters
(living close to)
Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville Average
Memphis (42%) 100 15 10 0 31.25
Nashville (26%) 0 100 20 15 33.75
Chattanooga (15%) 0 15 100 35 37.5
Knoxville (17%) 0 15 40 100 38.75

Using these utilities, voters will choose their optimal strategic votes based on what they think the various pivot probababilities are for pairwise ties. In each of the scenarios summarized below, all voters share a common set of pivot probabilities.

Approval Voting Results
for scenarios using optimal strategic voting
  Candidate Vote Totals
Strategy Scenario Winner Runner-up Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville
Zero-info Memphis Chattanooga 42 26 32 17
Memphis leading Chattanooga Three-way tie 42 58 58 58
Chattanooga leading Knoxville Chattanooga Nashville 42 68 83 17
Chattanooga leading Nashville Nashville Memphis 42 68 32 17
Nashville leading Memphis Nashville Memphis 42 58 32 32

In the first scenario, voters all choose their votes without any knowledge of, or at least without any regard for, how other voters might vote. As a result, they vote for any candidate with an above-average utility. Most voters vote for only their first choice. Only the Knoxville faction also votes for its second choice, Chattanooga. As a result, the winner is Memphis, the Condorcet loser, with Chattanooga coming in second place.

In the second scenario, all of the voters expect that Memphis is the likely winner, that Chattanooga is the likely runner-up, and that the pivot probability for a Memphis-Chattanooga tie is much larger than the pivot probabilities of any other pair-wise ties. As a result, each voter will vote for any candidate that is more preferred than the leading candidate and will also vote for the leading candidate if that candidate is more preferred than the expected runner-up. Each of the remaining scenarios follows a similar pattern of expectations and voting strategies.

In the second scenario, there is a three-way tie for first place. This happens because the expected winner, Memphis, was the Condorcet loser and was also ranked last by any voter that did not rank it first.

Only in the last scenario does the actual winner and runner-up match the expected winner and runner-up. As a result, this can be considered a stable strategic voting scenario. In this scenario, the winner is also the Condorcet winner.

Other issues and comparisons[편집]

Advocates of approval voting often note that a single simple ballot can serve for single, multiple, or negative choices. It requires the voter to think carefully about whom or what they really accept, rather than trusting a system of tallying or compromising by formal ranking or counting.[출처 필요] Compromises happen but they are explicit, and chosen by the voter, not by the ballot counting.[출처 필요] Some features of approval voting include:

  • Unlike Condorcet method, instant-runoff voting, and other methods that require ranking candidates, approval voting does not require significant changes in ballot design, voting procedures or equipment, and it is easier for voters to use and understand.[출처 필요] This reduces problems with mismarked ballots, disputed results and recounts.[출처 필요]
  • Approval voting fails the majority criterion, because it is possible that the candidate most preferred by the majority of voters, for example, winning 80% in a plurality election, will lose, if 85% indicate another candidate is at least acceptable to them.
  • It provides less incentive for negative campaigning than many other systems, through the same incentive as instant runoff voting, Condorcet method, and Borda count.[출처 필요]
  • It allows voters to express tolerances but not preferences. Some political scientists[누가?] consider this a major advantage, especially where acceptable choices are more important than popular choices.
  • It is easily reversed as disapproval voting where a choice is disavowed, as is already required in other measures in politics (e.g. representative recall|). Such reversal, however, is only possible if all candidates are known prior to the election (i.e. no write-ins).
  • In contentious elections with a super-majority of voters who prefer their favorite candidate vastly over all others, approval voting tends to revert to plurality voting. Some voters will support only their single favored candidate when they perceive the other candidates to be poor compromises.

Multiple winners[편집]

Approval voting can be extended to multiple winner elections.

승인투표는 여러명의 당선자를 뽑는 선거에도 사용될 수 있다.

The naive way to do so is as block approval voting, a simple variant on block voting where each voter can select an unlimited number of candidates and the candidates with the most approval votes win. This does not provide proportional representation and is subject to the Burr dilemma, among other problems.

Ballot types[편집]

Approval ballots can be of at least four semi-distinct forms. The simplest form is a blank ballot where the names of supported candidates is written in by hand. A more structured ballot will list all the candidates and allow a mark or word to be made by each supported candidate. A more explicit structured ballot can list the candidates and give two choices by each. (Candidate list ballots can include spaces for write-in candidates as well.)

All four ballots are interchangeable. The more structured ballots may aid voters in offering clear votes so they explicitly know all their choices. The Yes/No format can help to detect an "undervote" when a candidate is left unmarked and allow the voter a second chance to confirm the ballot markings are correct.

더 보기 See also[편집]

주석 References[편집]

  1. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, p. 3
  2. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1978). "Approval Voting". American Political Science Review 72(3): 831-847
  3. ,MAA Bylaws
  4. INFORMS bylaws p. 7
  5. ASA Bylaws
  6. Going from Theory to Practice: The Mixed Success of Approval Voting
  7. Lines, Marji (1986) "Approval Voting and Strategy Analysis: A Venetian Example" Theory and Decision 59: 155-172
  8. Analysis of voting method for election of Doges in Venice
  9. The Normative Turn in Public Choice, p. 4
  10. http://www.unsgselection.org/files/WisnumurtiGuidelinesSelectingCandidateSecretary-General.pdf
  11. Brams and Herschbach “The Science of Elections”. 《Science》 292 (5521): 1449. 2001. doi 10.1126/science.292.5521.1449.  |id=에 지움 문자가 있음(위치 66) (도움말)
  12. Results of experimental vote in France, 2002 (PDF|, French|)
  13. Nagel, J. H. (2007) "The Burr Dilemma in Approval Voting" The Journal of Politics 69(1): 43-58 [1]
  14. Nagel, J.H. (2006) "A Strategic Problem in Approval Voting," Mathematics and Democracy pp. 133-150. Studies in Choice and Welfare series (Springer)
  15. S. Brams and P. Fishburn. Going from Theory to Practice: The Mixed Success of Approval Voting (PDF|)
  16. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, p. 29
  17. Niemi, R.G. (1984) "The Problem of Strategic Behavior under Approval Voting" American Political Science Review 78(4) pp. 952-958
  18. Yilmaz, M.R. (1999) "Can we improve upon approval voting?," European Journal of Political Economy 15(1) pp. 89-100
  19. Saari, D.G. and Van Newenhizen, J. (2004) "The problem of indeterminancy in approval, multiple, and truncated voting systems", Public Choice 59(2) pp. 101-120
  20. Saari, D.G. and Van Newenhizen, J. (2004) "Is approval voting an ‘unmitigated evil?’ A response to Brams, Fishburn, and Merrill" Public Choice 59(2) pp. 133-147
  21. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, p. 31
  22. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, p. 38
  23. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, pp. 16-17
  24. Brams, S.J. and Remzi Sanver, M. (2005) "Critical strategies under approval voting: Who gets ruled in and ruled out," Electoral Studies 25(2) pp. 287-305
  25. Myerson, R. and Weber, R.J. (1993) "A theory of Voting Equilibria", American Political Science Review 87(1) pp. 102-114.
  26. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, p. 85
  27. Brams, Steven and Fishburn, Peter (1983). Approval Voting, Boston: Birkhauser, p. 74, 81
  28. Laslier, J.-F. (2006) "Strategic approval voting in a large electorate," IDEP Working Papers No. 405 (Marseille, France: Institut D'Economie Publique)

외부 링크 External links[편집]

틀:Wiktionarypar